郴州有什么好玩的景点| 为什么老是睡不着| 什么的梦| 甘是什么味道| 海淘是什么意思啊| 办理生育登记有什么用| 什么是碳酸饮料| 喜欢紫色代表什么| 开封有什么大学| 肝脏损伤会出现什么症状| 煲排骨汤放什么材料好| 黄痰是什么原因| 果代表什么生肖| 急性鼻窦炎吃什么药| 感冒为什么会打喷嚏| 什么锅好| 什么的遐想| 甲母痣挂什么科| 2007属什么| 没学历可以学什么技术| sr是什么意思| 动脉硬化是什么意思| 85年五行属什么| 省军区司令员是什么级别| 夜里12点是什么时辰| 两面三刀是什么生肖| 江米是什么米| 天网是什么意思| 孝服是什么意思| 甘油三酯高是什么原因| 梦见买猪肉是什么预兆| 早餐吃什么不会胖| 孕妇梦见掉牙齿是什么意思| 蝙蝠是什么类动物| 囊肿是什么原因引起的| 麻鸡是什么鸡| 三焦是什么器官| 盛产是什么意思| 补气养阴是什么意思| 晕车是什么原因引起的| 玉谷叶是什么植物| 为什么同房会痛| 怀孕前三个月要注意什么| 马路上的菱形标志是什么意思| 出人头地是什么意思| 肺肿瘤吃什么好| ipada1474是什么型号| 为什么会漏尿| 什么飞扬| 甲状腺过氧化物酶抗体高说明什么问题| 为什么腋下老是出汗| 什么饮料不含糖| 什么是沙眼| 活塞是什么意思| 乳腺小叶增生是什么意思| ptc是什么意思| 鱼腥草长什么样| 疹子长什么样| 粉丝炒什么好吃| 什么行业赚钱| 射手座是什么性格| 更年期什么时候开始| 药流有什么危害| 什么室什么空| 黄精有什么功效| 签证是什么| 四大天王叫什么名字| 眼压高什么症状| 黄酒什么味道| 身份证后4位代表什么| 风生水起是什么生肖| m蛋白是什么| 长痘不能吃什么| 什么桂什么香| 彩礼是什么意思| 青津果的功效是什么| 酒石酸美托洛尔片治什么病| 高血压喝什么茶| 头疼吃什么药好| 镶牙和种牙有什么区别| 胆固醇偏高有什么危害| 博美犬吃什么狗粮最好| 帕金森是什么| 腰肌劳损是什么原因造成的| absolue是兰蔻的什么产品| 做梦踩到屎是什么意思| 右脚踝肿是什么原因引起的| 附子是什么| 33周岁属什么生肖| 吃什么可以解决便秘| 外泌体是什么| 细菌感染吃什么抗生素| 咽喉充血是什么原因| 宫颈出血是什么症状| 什么是软文| 胆囊是干什么用的| 梦见老鼠是什么预兆| 软卧代软座什么意思| 清宫和刮宫有什么区别| 眼皮肿是什么原因| 什么食物含硒量最高| 吃毓婷有什么副作用| 花椒泡脚有什么功效| 舌头下面的筋叫什么| 面瘫是什么引起的| 女性得疱疹是什么症状| 韫字五行属什么| 胎儿双侧肾盂无分离是什么意思| 胃寒可以吃什么水果| 水银中毒会出现什么状况| 平肝潜阳是什么意思| 21金维他什么时候吃效果最好| 大难不死的生肖是什么| 指甲变空是什么原因| 痰多吃什么好化痰| 10.30什么星座| 什么是二型糖尿病| 记性差是什么原因| 恶对什么| 什么叫闺蜜| 神经性皮炎用什么药膏效果最好| 龙肉指的是什么肉| 妈妈的弟弟的老婆叫什么| 灼热感是什么样的感觉| 十二指肠溃疡吃什么中成药| 低密度脂蛋白高是什么原因| 北字五行属什么| 额头长闭口是什么原因| 马虎眼什么意思| 女人人中深代表什么| nc是什么| 抑郁看病看什么科| 检查头部挂什么科室| 过劳肥是什么意思| 乳头大是什么原因| 张什么结什么| 除氯是什么意思| 女性尿路感染吃什么药好得快| 眉毛里面长痘痘是什么原因| 数字7的风水含义是什么| 杀阴虱用什么药最好| 拜读是什么意思| 人格魅力什么意思| 为什么全麻手术后不能睡觉| 优势卵泡是什么意思| 慧外秀中什么意思| 刻舟求剑是什么生肖| 结肠多发息肉是什么意思| 五楼五行属什么| blingbling什么意思| 看痘痘挂什么科| 三点水一个高念什么| m什么意思| 咳嗽去医院挂什么科| 后羿和嫦娥是什么关系| 为什么乳头会变硬| 着床出血是什么样的| 牛欢喜是什么| 二进宫是什么意思| 人为什么会发热| 剥离是什么意思| 大什么| 包饺子剩下的面团能做什么| 女人为什么会叫| 夜宵吃什么不会胖| 薄荷有什么功效和作用| 逆行是什么意思| m1是什么单位| 五福是什么生肖| 普拉提是什么意思| 淡盐水漱口有什么好处| 喉咙痛流鼻涕吃什么药| 精神紊乱吃什么药| 嘴巴里发苦是什么原因| up主是什么意思| 股癣用什么药膏效果最好| 抗角蛋白抗体阳性是什么意思| 阑尾炎检查什么项目| 什么是猝死| 心率过低吃什么药| 什么是面瘫| 吃什么容易导致流产| 宫颈活检lsil是什么病| s属性什么意思| 息影是什么意思| 为什么尿是黄的| 安乃近是什么药| 洗内裤用什么洗比较好| 预拌粉是什么东西| 70属什么生肖| 什么相关四字成语| 圣贤是什么意思| 现在是什么时辰| 10.19什么星座| 反酸吃什么药| 表哥的女儿叫什么| 手痒脱皮是什么原因| 吐槽是什么意思| 周岁是什么意思| 什么叫统招生| 弯了是什么意思| 嗣读什么| 为什么脸一边大一边小| 荷尔蒙是什么意思| 缺钙会出现什么症状| 纹眉需要注意什么| 丁字是什么意思| 枕神经痛吃什么药| 红细胞阳性是什么意思| 10月4日是什么星座| 热脸贴冷屁股是什么意思| 什么人不能喝桑黄| 合掌是什么意思| 智人是什么意思| 人这一生为了什么| 缺铁吃什么补得最快| 干巴爹什么意思| 小孩咳嗽吃什么药效果最好| 补办身份证要带什么| 脚扭了挂什么科| 手痒脱皮是什么原因| 胆囊切除后有什么影响| 他达拉非是什么药| 晒伤用什么药| 非私营单位是什么| 悟空是什么意思| 恏是什么意思| 小腿酸什么原因| 1991年属羊是什么命| 人为什么会怕鬼| 体征是什么意思| 腔梗和脑梗有什么区别| 聚聚什么意思| s是什么m是什么| 鸡蛋和什么不能一起吃| 24号来月经什么时候是排卵期| 饭局是什么意思| 紫藤什么时候开花| 性格好的女生是什么样| 吃什么补钾食物有哪些| 唇炎抹什么药膏最有效| 白蛋白低是什么原因| 孩子呕吐是什么原因| 袁崇焕为什么杀毛文龙| 火车动车高铁有什么区别| 老人喝什么牛奶比较好| 3月21日是什么星座| 肝囊肿挂什么科| 3.4是什么星座| 头顶是什么穴位| 小狗发烧吃什么药| 竖中指代表什么意思| 头胀痛吃什么药| 蝴蝶宝贝是什么病| lof什么意思| 水色是什么颜色| 大圣是什么生肖| 二甲双胍缓释片什么时候吃最好| 大肠在人体什么位置图| 社保断交有什么影响| giada是什么牌子| 什么人不能喝咖啡| 高铁二等座是什么意思| 书是什么排比句| 百度Jump to content

【中字】特松加谈新任奶爸心得 回到家即充满爱

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
The number is irrational.
百度 新车的长宽高分别为4730mm/1824mm/1421mm,轴距达到了2860mm,相比较现款车型增加了85mm。

In mathematics, the irrational numbers are all the real numbers that are not rational numbers. That is, irrational numbers cannot be expressed as the ratio of two integers. When the ratio of lengths of two line segments is an irrational number, the line segments are also described as being incommensurable, meaning that they share no "measure" in common, that is, there is no length ("the measure"), no matter how short, that could be used to express the lengths of both of the two given segments as integer multiples of itself.

Among irrational numbers are the ratio π of a circle's circumference to its diameter, Euler's number e, the golden ratio φ, and the square root of two.[1] In fact, all square roots of natural numbers, other than of perfect squares, are irrational.[2]

Like all real numbers, irrational numbers can be expressed in positional notation, notably as a decimal number. In the case of irrational numbers, the decimal expansion does not terminate, nor end with a repeating sequence. For example, the decimal representation of π starts with 3.14159, but no finite number of digits can represent π exactly, nor does it repeat. Conversely, a decimal expansion that terminates or repeats must be a rational number. These are provable properties of rational numbers and positional number systems and are not used as definitions in mathematics.

Irrational numbers can also be expressed as non-terminating continued fractions (which in some cases are periodic), and in many other ways.

As a consequence of Cantor's proof that the real numbers are uncountable and the rationals countable, it follows that almost all real numbers are irrational.[3]

History

[edit]
An Euler diagram showing the set of real numbers (), which include the rationals (), which include the integers (), which include the natural numbers (). The real numbers also include the irrationals (\).

Ancient Greece

[edit]

The first proof of the existence of irrational numbers is usually attributed to a Pythagorean (possibly Hippasus of Metapontum),[4] who probably discovered them while identifying sides of the pentagram.[5] The Pythagorean method would have claimed that there must be some sufficiently small, indivisible unit that could fit evenly into one of these lengths as well as the other. Hippasus in the 5th century BC, however, was able to deduce that there was no common unit of measure, and that the assertion of such an existence was a contradiction. He did this by demonstrating that if the hypotenuse of an isosceles right triangle was indeed commensurable with a leg, then one of those lengths measured in that unit of measure must be both odd and even, which is impossible. His reasoning is as follows:

  • Start with an isosceles right triangle with side lengths of integers a, b, and c (a = b since it is isosceles). The ratio of the hypotenuse to a leg is represented by c:b.
  • Assume a, b, and c are in the smallest possible terms (i.e. they have no common factors).
  • By the Pythagorean theorem: c2 = a2+b2 = b2+b2 = 2b2. (Since the triangle is isosceles, a = b).
  • Since c2 = 2b2, c2 is divisible by 2, and therefore even.
  • Since c2 is even, c must be even.
  • Since c is even, dividing c by 2 yields an integer. Let y be this integer (c = 2y).
  • Squaring both sides of c = 2y yields c2 = (2y)2, or c2 = 4y2.
  • Substituting 4y2 for c2 in the first equation (c2 = 2b2) gives us 4y2= 2b2.
  • Dividing by 2 yields 2y2 = b2.
  • Since y is an integer, and 2y2 = b2, b2 is divisible by 2, and therefore even.
  • Since b2 is even, b must be even.
  • We have just shown that both b and c must be even. Hence they have a common factor of 2. However, this contradicts the assumption that they have no common factors. This contradiction proves that c and b cannot both be integers and thus the existence of a number that cannot be expressed as a ratio of two integers.[6]

Greek mathematicians termed this ratio of incommensurable magnitudes alogos, or inexpressible. Hippasus, however, was not lauded for his efforts: according to one legend, he made his discovery while out at sea, and was subsequently thrown overboard by his fellow Pythagoreans 'for having produced an element in the universe which denied the... doctrine that all phenomena in the universe can be reduced to whole numbers and their ratios.'[7] Another legend states that Hippasus was merely exiled for this revelation. Whatever the consequence to Hippasus himself, his discovery posed a very serious problem to Pythagorean mathematics, since it shattered the assumption that numbers and geometry were inseparable; a foundation of their theory.

The discovery of incommensurable ratios was indicative of another problem facing the Greeks: the relation of the discrete to the continuous. This was brought to light by Zeno of Elea, who questioned the conception that quantities are discrete and composed of a finite number of units of a given size. Past Greek conceptions dictated that they necessarily must be, for "whole numbers represent discrete objects, and a commensurable ratio represents a relation between two collections of discrete objects",[8] but Zeno found that in fact "[quantities] in general are not discrete collections of units; this is why ratios of incommensurable [quantities] appear... .[Q]uantities are, in other words, continuous".[8] What this means is that contrary to the popular conception of the time, there cannot be an indivisible, smallest unit of measure for any quantity. In fact, these divisions of quantity must necessarily be infinite. For example, consider a line segment: this segment can be split in half, that half split in half, the half of the half in half, and so on. This process can continue infinitely, for there is always another half to be split. The more times the segment is halved, the closer the unit of measure comes to zero, but it never reaches exactly zero. This is just what Zeno sought to prove. He sought to prove this by formulating four paradoxes, which demonstrated the contradictions inherent in the mathematical thought of the time. While Zeno's paradoxes accurately demonstrated the deficiencies of contemporary mathematical conceptions, they were not regarded as proof of the alternative. In the minds of the Greeks, disproving the validity of one view did not necessarily prove the validity of another, and therefore, further investigation had to occur.

The next step was taken by Eudoxus of Cnidus, who formalized a new theory of proportion that took into account commensurable as well as incommensurable quantities. Central to his idea was the distinction between magnitude and number. A magnitude "...was not a number but stood for entities such as line segments, angles, areas, volumes, and time which could vary, as we would say, continuously. Magnitudes were opposed to numbers, which jumped from one value to another, as from 4 to 5".[9] Numbers are composed of some smallest, indivisible unit, whereas magnitudes are infinitely reducible. Because no quantitative values were assigned to magnitudes, Eudoxus was then able to account for both commensurable and incommensurable ratios by defining a ratio in terms of its magnitude, and proportion as an equality between two ratios. By taking quantitative values (numbers) out of the equation, he avoided the trap of having to express an irrational number as a number. "Eudoxus' theory enabled the Greek mathematicians to make tremendous progress in geometry by supplying the necessary logical foundation for incommensurable ratios".[10] This incommensurability is dealt with in Euclid's Elements, Book X, Proposition 9. It was not until Eudoxus developed a theory of proportion that took into account irrational as well as rational ratios that a strong mathematical foundation of irrational numbers was created.[11]

As a result of the distinction between number and magnitude, geometry became the only method that could take into account incommensurable ratios. Because previous numerical foundations were still incompatible with the concept of incommensurability, Greek focus shifted away from numerical conceptions such as algebra and focused almost exclusively on geometry. In fact, in many cases, algebraic conceptions were reformulated into geometric terms. This may account for why we still conceive of x2 and x3 as x squared and x cubed instead of x to the second power and x to the third power. Also crucial to Zeno's work with incommensurable magnitudes was the fundamental focus on deductive reasoning that resulted from the foundational shattering of earlier Greek mathematics. The realization that some basic conception within the existing theory was at odds with reality necessitated a complete and thorough investigation of the axioms and assumptions that underlie that theory. Out of this necessity, Eudoxus developed his method of exhaustion, a kind of reductio ad absurdum that "...established the deductive organization on the basis of explicit axioms..." as well as "...reinforced the earlier decision to rely on deductive reasoning for proof".[12] This method of exhaustion is the first step in the creation of calculus.

Theodorus of Cyrene proved the irrationality of the surds of whole numbers up to 17, but stopped there probably because the algebra he used could not be applied to the square root of 17.[13]

India

[edit]

Geometrical and mathematical problems involving irrational numbers such as square roots were addressed very early during the Vedic period in India. There are references to such calculations in the Samhitas, Brahmanas, and the Shulba Sutras (800 BC or earlier).[14]

It is suggested that the concept of irrationality was implicitly accepted by Indian mathematicians since the 7th century BC, when Manava (c. 750 – 690 BC) believed that the square roots of numbers such as 2 and 61 could not be exactly determined.[15] Historian Carl Benjamin Boyer, however, writes that "such claims are not well substantiated and unlikely to be true".[16]

Later, in their treatises, Indian mathematicians wrote on the arithmetic of surds including addition, subtraction, multiplication, rationalization, as well as separation and extraction of square roots.[17]

Mathematicians like Brahmagupta (in 628 AD) and Bhāskara I (in 629 AD) made contributions in this area as did other mathematicians who followed. In the 12th century Bhāskara II evaluated some of these formulas and critiqued them, identifying their limitations.

During the 14th to 16th centuries, Madhava of Sangamagrama and the Kerala school of astronomy and mathematics discovered the infinite series for several irrational numbers such as π and certain irrational values of trigonometric functions. Jye??hadeva provided proofs for these infinite series in the Yuktibhā?ā.[18]

Islamic World

[edit]

In the Middle Ages, the development of algebra by Muslim mathematicians allowed irrational numbers to be treated as algebraic objects.[19] Middle Eastern mathematicians also merged the concepts of "number" and "magnitude" into a more general idea of real numbers, criticized Euclid's idea of ratios, developed the theory of composite ratios, and extended the concept of number to ratios of continuous magnitude.[20] In his commentary on Book 10 of the Elements, the Persian mathematician Al-Mahani (d. 874/884) examined and classified quadratic irrationals and cubic irrationals. He provided definitions for rational and irrational magnitudes, which he treated as irrational numbers. He dealt with them freely but explains them in geometric terms as follows:[20]

"It will be a rational (magnitude) when we, for instance, say 10, 12, 3%, 6%, etc., because its value is pronounced and expressed quantitatively. What is not rational is irrational and it is impossible to pronounce and represent its value quantitatively. For example: the roots of numbers such as 10, 15, 20 which are not squares, the sides of numbers which are not cubes etc."

In contrast to Euclid's concept of magnitudes as lines, Al-Mahani considered integers and fractions as rational magnitudes, and square roots and cube roots as irrational magnitudes. He also introduced an arithmetical approach to the concept of irrationality, as he attributes the following to irrational magnitudes:[20]

"their sums or differences, or results of their addition to a rational magnitude, or results of subtracting a magnitude of this kind from an irrational one, or of a rational magnitude from it."

The Egyptian mathematician Abū Kāmil Shujā ibn Aslam (c. 850 – 930) was the first to accept irrational numbers as solutions to quadratic equations or as coefficients in an equation in the form of square roots and fourth roots.[21] In the 10th century, the Iraqi mathematician Al-Hashimi provided general proofs (rather than geometric demonstrations) for irrational numbers, as he considered multiplication, division, and other arithmetical functions.[20]

Many of these concepts were eventually accepted by European mathematicians sometime after the Latin translations of the 12th century. Al-Hassār, a Moroccan mathematician from Fez specializing in Islamic inheritance jurisprudence during the 12th century, first mentions the use of a fractional bar, where numerators and denominators are separated by a horizontal bar. In his discussion he writes, "..., for example, if you are told to write three-fifths and a third of a fifth, write thus, ."[22] This same fractional notation appears soon after in the work of Leonardo Fibonacci in the 13th century.[23]

Modern period

[edit]

The 17th century saw imaginary numbers become a powerful tool in the hands of Abraham de Moivre, and especially of Leonhard Euler. The completion of the theory of complex numbers in the 19th century entailed the differentiation of irrationals into algebraic and transcendental numbers, the proof of the existence of transcendental numbers, and the resurgence of the scientific study of the theory of irrationals, largely ignored since Euclid. The year 1872 saw the publication of the theories of Karl Weierstrass (by his pupil Ernst Kossak), Eduard Heine (Crelle's Journal, 74), Georg Cantor (Annalen, 5), and Richard Dedekind. Méray had taken in 1869 the same point of departure as Heine, but the theory is generally referred to the year 1872. Weierstrass's method has been completely set forth by Salvatore Pincherle in 1880,[24] and Dedekind's has received additional prominence through the author's later work (1888) and the endorsement by Paul Tannery (1894). Weierstrass, Cantor, and Heine base their theories on infinite series, while Dedekind founds his on the idea of a cut (Schnitt) in the system of all rational numbers, separating them into two groups having certain characteristic properties. The subject has received later contributions at the hands of Weierstrass, Leopold Kronecker (Crelle, 101), and Charles Méray.

Continued fractions, closely related to irrational numbers (and due to Cataldi, 1613), received attention at the hands of Euler, and at the opening of the 19th century were brought into prominence through the writings of Joseph-Louis Lagrange. Dirichlet also added to the general theory, as have numerous contributors to the applications of the subject.

Johann Heinrich Lambert proved (1761) that π cannot be rational, and that en is irrational if n is rational (unless n = 0).[25] While Lambert's proof is often called incomplete, modern assessments support it as satisfactory, and in fact for its time it is unusually rigorous. Adrien-Marie Legendre (1794), after introducing the Bessel–Clifford function, provided a proof to show that π2 is irrational, whence it follows immediately that π is irrational also. The existence of transcendental numbers was first established by Liouville (1844, 1851). Later, Georg Cantor (1873) proved their existence by a different method, which showed that every interval in the reals contains transcendental numbers. Charles Hermite (1873) first proved e transcendental, and Ferdinand von Lindemann (1882), starting from Hermite's conclusions, showed the same for π. Lindemann's proof was much simplified by Weierstrass (1885), still further by David Hilbert (1893), and was finally made elementary by Adolf Hurwitz[citation needed] and Paul Gordan.[26]

Examples

[edit]

Square roots

[edit]

The square root of 2 was likely the first number proved irrational.[27] The golden ratio is another famous quadratic irrational number. The square roots of all natural numbers that are not perfect squares are irrational and a proof may be found in quadratic irrationals.

General roots

[edit]

The proof for the irrationality of the square root of two can be generalized using the fundamental theorem of arithmetic. This asserts that every integer has a unique factorization into primes. Using it we can show that if a rational number is not an integer then no integral power of it can be an integer, as in lowest terms there must be a prime in the denominator that does not divide into the numerator whatever power each is raised to. Therefore, if an integer is not an exact kth power of another integer, then that first integer's kth root is irrational.

Logarithms

[edit]

Perhaps the numbers most easy to prove irrational are certain logarithms. Here is a proof by contradiction that log2 3 is irrational (log2 3 ≈ 1.58 > 0).

Assume log2 3 is rational. For some positive integers m and n, we have

It follows that

The number 2 raised to any positive integer power must be even (because it is divisible by 2) and the number 3 raised to any positive integer power must be odd (since none of its prime factors will be 2). Clearly, an integer cannot be both odd and even at the same time: we have a contradiction. The only assumption we made was that log2 3 is rational (and so expressible as a quotient of integers m/n with n ≠ 0). The contradiction means that this assumption must be false, i.e. log2 3 is irrational, and can never be expressed as a quotient of integers m/n with n ≠ 0.

Cases such as log10 2 can be treated similarly.

Types

[edit]

An irrational number may be algebraic, that is a real root of a polynomial with integer coefficients. Those that are not algebraic are transcendental.

Algebraic

[edit]

The real algebraic numbers are the real solutions of polynomial equations

where the coefficients are integers and . An example of an irrational algebraic number is x0 = (21/2 + 1)1/3. It is clearly algebraic since it is the root of an integer polynomial, , which is equivalent to . This polynomial has no rational roots, since the rational root theorem shows that the only possibilities are ±1, but x0 is greater than 1. So x0 is an irrational algebraic number. There are countably many algebraic numbers, since there are countably many integer polynomials.

Transcendental

[edit]

Almost all irrational numbers are transcendental. Examples are e r and π r, which are transcendental for all nonzero rational r.

Because the algebraic numbers form a subfield of the real numbers, many irrational real numbers can be constructed by combining transcendental and algebraic numbers. For example, 3π + 2, π + 2 and e3 are irrational (and even transcendental).

Decimal expansions

[edit]

The decimal expansion of an irrational number never repeats (meaning the decimal expansion does not repeat the same number or sequence of numbers) or terminates (this means there is not a finite number of nonzero digits), unlike any rational number. The same is true for binary, octal or hexadecimal expansions, and in general for expansions in every positional notation with natural bases.

To show this, suppose we divide integers n by m (where m is nonzero). When long division is applied to the division of n by m, there can never be a remainder greater than or equal to m. If 0 appears as a remainder, the decimal expansion terminates. If 0 never occurs, then the algorithm can run at most m ? 1 steps without using any remainder more than once. After that, a remainder must recur, and then the decimal expansion repeats.

Conversely, suppose we are faced with a repeating decimal, we can prove that it is a fraction of two integers. For example, consider:

Here the repetend is 162 and the length of the repetend is 3. First, we multiply by an appropriate power of 10 to move the decimal point to the right so that it is just in front of a repetend. In this example we would multiply by 10 to obtain:

Now we multiply this equation by 10r where r is the length of the repetend. This has the effect of moving the decimal point to be in front of the "next" repetend. In our example, multiply by 103:

The result of the two multiplications gives two different expressions with exactly the same "decimal portion", that is, the tail end of 10,000A matches the tail end of 10A exactly. Here, both 10,000A and 10A have .162162162... after the decimal point.

Therefore, when we subtract the 10A equation from the 10,000A equation, the tail end of 10A cancels out the tail end of 10,000A leaving us with:

Then

is a ratio of integers and therefore a rational number.

Irrational powers

[edit]

Dov Jarden gave a simple non-constructive proof that there exist two irrational numbers a and b, such that ab is rational:[28][29]

Consider ; if this is rational, then take a = b = . Otherwise, take a to be the irrational number and b = . Then ab = () · , which is rational.

Although the above argument does not decide between the two cases, the Gelfond–Schneider theorem shows that is transcendental, hence irrational. This theorem states that if a and b are both algebraic numbers, and a is not equal to 0 or 1, and b is not a rational number, then any value of ab is a transcendental number (there can be more than one value if complex number exponentiation is used).

An example that provides a simple constructive proof is[30]

The base of the left side is irrational and the right side is rational, so one must prove that the exponent on the left side, , is irrational. This is so because, by the formula relating logarithms with different bases,

which we can assume, for the sake of establishing a contradiction, equals a ratio m/n of positive integers. Then hence hence hence , which is a contradictory pair of prime factorizations and hence violates the fundamental theorem of arithmetic (unique prime factorization).

A stronger result is the following:[31] Every rational number in the interval can be written either as aa for some irrational number a or as nn for some natural number n. Similarly,[31] every positive rational number can be written either as for some irrational number a or as for some natural number n.

Open questions

[edit]

In constructive mathematics

[edit]

In constructive mathematics, excluded middle is not valid, so it is not true that every real number is rational or irrational. Thus, the notion of an irrational number bifurcates into multiple distinct notions. One could take the traditional definition of an irrational number as a real number that is not rational.[35] However, there is a second definition of an irrational number used in constructive mathematics, that a real number is an irrational number if it is apart from every rational number, or equivalently, if the distance between and every rational number is positive. This definition is stronger than the traditional definition of an irrational number. This second definition is used in Errett Bishop's proof that the square root of 2 is irrational.[36]

Set of all irrationals

[edit]

Since the reals form an uncountable set, of which the rationals are a countable subset, the complementary set of irrationals is uncountable.

Under the usual (Euclidean) distance function , the real numbers are a metric space and hence also a topological space. Restricting the Euclidean distance function gives the irrationals the structure of a metric space. Since the subspace of irrationals is not closed, the induced metric is not complete. Being a G-delta set—i.e., a countable intersection of open subsets—in a complete metric space, the space of irrationals is completely metrizable: that is, there is a metric on the irrationals inducing the same topology as the restriction of the Euclidean metric, but with respect to which the irrationals are complete. One can see this without knowing the aforementioned fact about G-delta sets: the continued fraction expansion of an irrational number defines a homeomorphism from the space of irrationals to the space of all sequences of positive integers, which is easily seen to be completely metrizable.

Furthermore, the set of all irrationals is a disconnected metrizable space. In fact, the irrationals equipped with the subspace topology have a basis of clopen groups so the space is zero-dimensional.

See also

[edit]
Number systems
Complex
Real
Rational
Integer
Natural
Zero: 0
One: 1
Prime numbers
Composite numbers
Negative integers
Fraction
Finite decimal
Dyadic (finite binary)
Repeating decimal
Irrational
Algebraic irrational
Irrational period
Transcendental
Imaginary

References

[edit]
  1. ^ The 15 Most Famous Transcendental Numbers. by Clifford A. Pickover. URL retrieved 24 October 2007.
  2. ^ Jackson, Terence (2025-08-06). "95.42 Irrational square roots of natural numbers — a geometrical approach". The Mathematical Gazette. 95 (533): 327–330. doi:10.1017/S0025557200003193. ISSN 0025-5572. S2CID 123995083.
  3. ^ Cantor, Georg (1955) [1915]. Philip Jourdain (ed.). Contributions to the Founding of the Theory of Transfinite Numbers. New York: Dover. ISBN 978-0-486-60045-1. {{cite book}}: ISBN / Date incompatibility (help)
  4. ^ Kurt Von Fritz (1945). "The Discovery of Incommensurability by Hippasus of Metapontum". Annals of Mathematics. 46 (2): 242–264. doi:10.2307/1969021. JSTOR 1969021. S2CID 126296119.
  5. ^ James R. Choike (1980). "The Pentagram and the Discovery of an Irrational Number". The Two-Year College Mathematics Journal. 11 (5): 312–316. doi:10.2307/3026893. JSTOR 3026893. S2CID 115390951.
  6. ^ Kline, M. (1990). Mathematical Thought from Ancient to Modern Times, Vol. 1. New York: Oxford University Press (original work published 1972), p. 33.
  7. ^ Kline 1990, p. 32.
  8. ^ a b Kline 1990, p. 34.
  9. ^ Kline 1990, p. 48.
  10. ^ Kline 1990, p. 49.
  11. ^ Charles H. Edwards (1982). The historical development of the calculus. Springer.
  12. ^ Kline 1990, p. 50.
  13. ^ Robert L. McCabe (1976). "Theodorus' Irrationality Proofs". Mathematics Magazine. 49 (4): 201–203. doi:10.1080/0025570X.1976.11976579. JSTOR 2690123. S2CID 124565880..
  14. ^ Bag, Amulya Kumar (1990). "Ritual Geometry in India and its Parallelism in other Culture Areas". Indian Journal of History of Science. 25.
  15. ^ T. K. Puttaswamy, "The Accomplishments of Ancient Indian Mathematicians", pp. 411–2, in Selin, Helaine; D'Ambrosio, Ubiratan, eds. (2000). Mathematics Across Cultures: The History of Non-western Mathematics. Springer. ISBN 1-4020-0260-2..
  16. ^ Boyer (1991). "China and India". A History of Mathematics (2nd ed.). Wiley. p. 208. ISBN 0471093742. OCLC 414892. It has been claimed also that the first recognition of incommensurables appears in India during the Sulbasutra period, but such claims are not well substantiated. The case for early Hindu awareness of incommensurable magnitudes is rendered most unlikely by the lack of evidence that Indian mathematicians of that period had come to grips with fundamental concepts.
  17. ^ Datta, Bibhutibhusan; Singh, Awadhesh Narayan (1993). "Surds in Hindu mathematics" (PDF). Indian Journal of History of Science. 28 (3): 253–264. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2025-08-06. Retrieved 18 September 2018.
  18. ^ Katz, V. J. (1995). "Ideas of Calculus in Islam and India". Mathematics Magazine. 63 (3): 163–174. doi:10.2307/2691411. JSTOR 2691411.
  19. ^ O'Connor, John J.; Robertson, Edmund F. (1999). "Arabic mathematics: forgotten brilliance?". MacTutor History of Mathematics Archive. University of St Andrews..
  20. ^ a b c d Matvievskaya, Galina (1987). "The theory of quadratic irrationals in medieval Oriental mathematics". Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences. 500 (1): 253–277. Bibcode:1987NYASA.500..253M. doi:10.1111/j.1749-6632.1987.tb37206.x. S2CID 121416910. See in particular pp. 254 & 259–260.
  21. ^ Jacques Sesiano, "Islamic mathematics", p. 148, in Selin, Helaine; D'Ambrosio, Ubiratan (2000). Mathematics Across Cultures: The History of Non-western Mathematics. Springer. ISBN 1-4020-0260-2..
  22. ^ Cajori, Florian (1928). A History of Mathematical Notations (Vol.1). La Salle, Illinois: The Open Court Publishing Company. pg. 269.
  23. ^ (Cajori 1928, pg.89)
  24. ^ Salvatore Pincherle (1880). "Saggio di una introduzione alla teoria delle funzioni analitiche secondo i principii del prof. C. Weierstrass". Giornale di Matematiche: 178–254, 317–320.
  25. ^ Lambert, J. H. (1761). "Mémoire sur quelques propriétés remarquables des quantités transcendentes, circulaires et logarithmiques" (PDF). Mémoires de l'Académie royale des sciences de Berlin (in French): 265–322. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2025-08-06.
  26. ^ Gordan, Paul (1893). "Transcendenz von e und π". Mathematische Annalen. 43 (2–3). Teubner: 222–224. doi:10.1007/bf01443647. S2CID 123203471.
  27. ^ Fowler, David H. (2001), "The story of the discovery of incommensurability, revisited", Neusis (10): 45–61, MR 1891736
  28. ^ Jarden, Dov (1953). "Curiosa No. 339: A simple proof that a power of an irrational number to an irrational exponent may be rational". Scripta Mathematica. 19: 229. copy
  29. ^ George, Alexander; Velleman, Daniel J. (2002). Philosophies of mathematics (PDF). Blackwell. pp. 3–4. ISBN 0-631-19544-0.
  30. ^ Lord, Nick, "Maths bite: irrational powers of irrational numbers can be rational", Mathematical Gazette 92, November 2008, p. 534.
  31. ^ a b Marshall, Ash J., and Tan, Yiren, "A rational number of the form aa with a irrational", Mathematical Gazette 96, March 2012, pp. 106-109.
  32. ^ Waldschmidt, Michel (2021). "Schanuel's Conjecture: algebraic independence of transcendental numbers" (PDF).
  33. ^ Waldschmidt, Michel (2023). "Some of the most famous open problems in number theory" (PDF).
  34. ^ Waldschmidt, Michel (2022). "Transcendental Number Theory: recent results and open problems". Michel Waldschmidt.
  35. ^ Mark Bridger (2007). Real Analysis: A Constructive Approach through Interval Arithmetic. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 978-1-470-45144-8.
  36. ^ Errett Bishop; Douglas Bridges (1985). Constructive Analysis. Springer. ISBN 0-387-15066-8.

Further reading

[edit]
  • Adrien-Marie Legendre, éléments de Géometrie, Note IV, (1802), Paris
  • Rolf Wallisser, "On Lambert's proof of the irrationality of π", in Algebraic Number Theory and Diophantine Analysis, Franz Halter-Koch and Robert F. Tichy, (2000), Walter de Gruyter
[edit]
月经淋漓不尽什么原因 清朝什么时候建立 肝气虚吃什么中成药 每天起床口苦口臭是什么原因 婧字五行属什么
damon英文名什么寓意 做nt挂什么科 蒙脱石散是什么 圣经是什么意思 阴虱长什么样子
什么茶可以减肥 儿童过敏性结膜炎用什么眼药水 leep术是什么手术 经常恶心干呕是什么原因 什么的城堡
低密度脂蛋白偏高什么意思 学英语先从什么学起 面霜和乳液有什么区别 什么是汛期 pdi是什么
心肌缺血做什么检查能查出来hcv9jop6ns2r.cn 三七有什么功效hcv9jop1ns6r.cn 下午三点到五点是什么时辰hcv8jop0ns7r.cn 鲫鱼不能和什么一起吃hcv9jop7ns0r.cn 脖子下面的骨头叫什么hcv8jop6ns1r.cn
什么牌子的耳机音质效果最好clwhiglsz.com 肚子胀吃什么药0735v.com 家蛇出现寓意什么hcv8jop0ns6r.cn 胃发胀是什么原因hcv9jop5ns9r.cn 吃米饭配什么菜好吃hcv7jop6ns6r.cn
为什么乳头会变黑jingluanji.com 梦见把蛇打死了是什么意思yanzhenzixun.com 睡眠障碍吃什么药最好qingzhougame.com 玻尿酸是干什么用的hcv8jop2ns0r.cn miss什么意思hcv9jop0ns5r.cn
怀疑哮喘要做什么检查hcv7jop4ns7r.cn 黄色五行属什么hcv8jop4ns6r.cn 青筋明显是什么原因hcv9jop1ns2r.cn 女性分泌物发黄是什么原因wuhaiwuya.com 眼睛长麦粒肿用什么药hcv8jop7ns1r.cn
百度